:thumb:
This has really been my point. I played along in an attempt to show quip that the hypothetical had nothing to do with my position specifically and little to do with abortion in general.
I use to love hypotheticals, then I read about one that I frequently used - the train switching dilemma.
Basically, a mad ethics professor kidnaps six people, ties 5 of them to a railroad track, and the 6th to another railroad track. Then sets a runaway train towards the group of 5. You are at a remote station, but can push a button to switch the train over to the track with only one person. Most people would push that button, even though they would be intentionally killing that one person (to save the other 5).
Seems pretty clear cut, most people agree that intentionally causing the death of an innocent is sometimes justified. Right?
But change the case slightly - instead of one person tied to the track, pushing the button would derail the train, causing it to kill a guy sleeping in a hammock outside his house. Same moral decision, yet this time most people would not press the button (unless they were asked the former hypothetical first - then they would keep their answers consistent!).
Change the hypothetical again - this time there is no switch, but you can push a severely obese man in front of the train, killing him but saving the 5. Almost no one would make that choice, despite it being "morally equivalent".
In short, subtle changes can be used to get the result you want.
With abortion, the problem is compounded. There is no hypothetical that does a good job of portraying the factors involved. Any hypothetical offered is either inapplicable, deals with only one facet of the moral decision, overemphasizes or flat out replaces a factor, or is so foreign to our innate moral compass that we can't make a reasonable judgement. Many times hypotheticals are all of those.
----------------------------------
The only (arguably) useful aspect of hypotheticals is in proving the folly of most blanket universal moral statements.